Read online free
  • Home
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    The Book of Memory

    Prev Next


      standing of the cognitive function of memory. To have forgotten things is

      seen by us now as a failure of knowledge, however ordinary a failure it may

      be, and therefore a reason to distrust the power of memory altogether. Yet

      to have forgotten some things was understood in Augustine’s culture as a

      necessary condition for remembering others. It is helpful to distinguish two

      sorts of forgetting, resulting from different causes. There is the kind that

      results from failing to imprint something in the first place – the sort

      Augustine seems to be talking about here. This should not even be called

      forgetting because, as Aristotle remarked in his discussion of memory and

      recollection, one cannot be properly said to have forgotten something that

      was never there in the first place.

      On the other hand, there is deliberate or selective forgetting, the sort of

      forgetting that itself results from an activity of memory. In the passage

      I have just quoted, Augustine is certainly speaking of a consciously trained

      memory, one whose denizens, like prey (for he often speaks of memories as

      being like animals hunted from their lairs, whose tracks or vestiges are to be

      followed through their familiar pathways in the forest), can be rationally

      sought out via their particular paths when needed for use, and then

      returned to their proper places when finished with. But this edifice, this

      vast treasury, is chosen and constructed. It is a work of art, using the

      materials of nature as all arts do, but consciously crafted for some human

      use and purpose.

      In his book on Memory, History, Forgetting, the French philosopher Paul

      Ricoeur, himself a profound student of Augustine, complained that arts of

      memory are ‘‘an outrageous denial of forgetfulness and . . . of the weaknesses

      inherent in both the preservation of [memory] traces and their evocation.’’2

      In a similar vein, Harald Weinrich in Lethe, a book that sweeps engagingly

      over the theme of forgetting in canonical Western literature, states that ars

      xii

      Preface to the second edition

      memorativa represents itself to be ‘ an art that can serve to overcome forget-

      ting.’’3 And he archly observes that in its celebrated advice about making

      multi-compartmental structures for a rich trove of remembered matters,

      ‘ only forgetting has no place.’’ But, as Augustine makes abundantly clear,

      Weinrich is wrong about that. Not only does forgetting have its honored

      place in an examination of memoria – indeed Augustine devotes a whole

      section of his discussion to the paradox that he can remember that he has

      forgotten something (Confessions X.16) – but forgetting, of a sort, is essential

      to constructing an art of memory in the first place.

      Aristotle distinguishes clearly between the objects of memory and the

      investigative search, in his treatise ‘‘On memory and recollection’’ in the

      Parva naturalia, a matter I have dwelt on at some length in Chapter 2, and

      that is fundamental to all later analysis of the psychological processes of

      memory. This distinction is germane to the seeming lack of concern with

      forgetting in pre-modern teaching on memory, because the main focus of

      the arts of memory is on recollection – the search for stuff already there–

      and not on the representation of the object remembered. One can dem-

      onstrate this emphasis from the so-called artes oblivionales found in a few

      late humanist treatises on memory art. The ‘‘oblivion’’ discussed is to

      do with how to refresh one’s search networks, not with worries about

      the accuracy or partialness of one’s memories. As Lina Bolzoni has

      commented, ‘‘The techniques for forgetting handed down by the treatises

      are testimony to the persistence and power of the images,’’ for they address

      the tasks of sorting out and reducing the number of memory places rather

      than with suppressing or otherwise editing content one has previously

      learned. 4

      Another matter to which the first edition gave much too short a shrift is

      the place of rote memorization – memorizing by heart – in the edifice of an

      ancient and medieval education. Most students of the arts of memory

      (including, when I began, me) have made a basic error when considering

      the relationship of memory craft to rote learning, by thinking both to be

      methods for initially memorizing the basic contents of educated memory.

      We have all been in good company in this confusion, for even the

      seventeenth-century Jesuit, Matteo Ricci, who practiced an art of memory,

      elided the two when he tried to teach his art as a helpful device for passing

      the content-based examinations of the Chinese imperial civil service. 5

      Where this analysis went wrong was in supposing that learning an art for

      memory was intended as an alternative to rote learning, and in misunder-

      standing the ancient mnemotechnical term memoria verborum as a syno-

      nym for the verbatim memorization of long texts.

      Preface to the second edition

      xiii

      Matteo Ricci’s Chinese hosts were on the right track when they com-

      plained that memorizing a scheme of memory places and cues added far too

      burdensome and confusing a task to the already difficult one of memorizing

      by rote – why memorize things twice? Why indeed. That simple question is

      the heart of the matter. In revising The Book of Memory, I have tried to set out

      the answer plainly in Chapter 3, during my discussion of Hugh of St Victor’s

      preface to his elementary tables of the names and dates of Biblical history,

      addressed to the pueri or students of St. Victor in about 1135, after he had

      composed Didascalicon, his treatise on the goals and methods of education.6

      It is with some chagrin that I realize now how wrong I was about this and

      for how long. When I first came across Hugh’s preface in the early 1980s,

      I recognized that it offered the clearest presentation of an art of memory

      extant, much clearer than that in the Rhetorica ad Herennium – and also

      completely different in its details, though not in its basic principles.

      Seeking to understand it, I spent several months, while commuting to

      work in Chicago on the elevated train, memorizing psalms with the

      method Hugh described. I attached pieces of the texts I already knew by

      heart to the places I had created by using a mentally imposed grid system

      which was exactly that of the chapter and verse scheme of a modern printed

      Bible. I realized quickly that doing so gave me complete flexibility and

      security in finding the verses again in whatever order I chose. I could

      reverse the order, pull out all the odd-numbered verses, or all the even-

      numbered ones, or alternate reciting the odd verses in forward order and

      the even ones in reverse. I could also mentally interleave and recite the

      verses of one psalm with those of another. Bewitched by my new-found

      skill (I even once began a lecture by interleaving the verses of Psalm 1 in

      reverse order with those of psalm 23 in forward order), I overlooked the fact

      that I wasn’t actually memorizing the words for the first time. I was instead

      imposing a divisional system onto something I already kn
    ew by heart.

      This was a crucial ingredient of the method’s success, though I failed to

      pay proper attention to it in my initial analysis. I did note that, for the

      quickest and most secure results, I needed to say the psalm text in English

      (and in the 1611 version which I learned as a child) and that I also needed to

      call up ‘ The Lord is my shepherd’ by its number in the Protestant Bible (23),

      not the Vulgate (22). What I was demonstrating was the power of such

      mental devices as finding tools rather than as retention devices. In fact, it

      was easy to impose such a scheme on material I already knew by heart (in

      King James English) because, with a bit of review and practice, the cues

      provided to my memory by just a few words of the texts I knew so securely

      brought out the whole quotation. Once started, my rote memory took over,

      xiv

      Preface to the second edition

      and by conscious habit produced what I needed, very much in the manner of

      the Read-Only memory of a computer. The recollection devices of mne-

      monic art, like a Random-Access structure, took me where I wanted to go, in

      the order I had chosen and in the directions my mind had given to itself.

      Many people have asked me over the years if memory arts really work.

      The answer to that is yes – if you know how to use them. They are not a pill

      or potion, and those who attempt to sell them as if they were are as

      fraudulent as any fake medicine purveyor. Nor can they be patented, or

      licensed to others like the secret recipe for a special sauce. All teachers of the

      subject, from the days of Cicero and his Greek masters, have made just

      these same points. It is amusing to me to read now in the science press some

      breathless accounts of how to improve memory by using the amazing

      Method of Loci, or to hear of efforts to introduce into schools a patented

      memory curriculum, guaranteeing improved learning for all. Some things

      never change . . .

      Certainly, were I to begin The Book of Memory today, I would do it

      differently, but that is the way of scholarship. I have left the Introduction to

      the first edition unchanged, partly to measure just how much good work

      has been done in the subject since those words were first written in 1989.

      Most of this work has come from historians – of art and architecture, of

      music, of rhetoric, of law, of reading and of the book, of monasticism and

      religion, and of literature both in Latin and in vernaculars – but some as

      well has come, gratifyingly if astonishingly to me, from psychologists,

      anthropologists, neuroscientists, and computer designers. It did not

      occur to me when I began the project that it would resonate so broadly,

      nor that I would find myself keeping delightful intellectual company for so

      long a time with so wide a spectrum of scholar-scientists. Their friendship

      and collegiality towards me and my subsequent work has nourished and

      enriched me more than I could ever hope to acknowledge adequately. Most

      appear in my notes and bibliography, the site of our continuing conversa-

      tions. One individual needs to be named: Linda Bree, literature editor at

      Cambridge University Press, who kept after me with unfailing good humor

      and gentle persistence until this work was done. Thank you. Three insti-

      tutions also should be thanked: the University of Oxford and its unparal-

      leled community of medievalists who have made me one of their own; the

      John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation, with whose support

      I was able to continue this work and begin new projects; and New York

      University, my familiar base in the city that has been my home for so long.

      Oxford and New York, 2007

      Abbreviations

      (Full citations for published titles are in the Bibliography.)

      AASS

      Acta Sanctorum

      Ad Her.

      [Cicero], Rhetorica ad Herennium

      AMRS

      Arizona Medieval and Renaissance Studies

      Avi. Lat.

      Avicenna (Ibn Sinna) latinus

      CCCM

      Corpus christianorum continuatio medievalis

      CCSL

      Corpus christianorum series latina

      CHB

      The Cambridge History of the Bible

      Conf.

      St. Augustine, Confessiones

      CSEL

      Corpus scriptorum ecclesiasticorum latinorum

      DTC

      Dictionnaire de theólogie catholique

      Du Cange

      C. Du Cange et al., Glossarium mediae et infimae

      latinitatis

      EETS

      The Early English Text Society

      Etym.

      Isidore of Seville, Etymologiarum libri

      Inst. orat.

      Quintilian, Institutio oratoria

      JMRS

      Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies

      (now Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies)

      JWCI

      Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes

      LCL

      Loeb Classical Library

      Lewis and Short

      C. T. Lewis and C. Short, A Latin Dictionary

      Liddell and Scott

      H. G. Liddell and R. Scott, A Greek–English Lexicon

      MED

      The Middle English Dictionary

      MGH

      Monumenta Germaniae historica

      MRTS

      Medieval and Renaissance Texts Series

      OED

      The Oxford English Dictionary

      Ox. Lat. Dict.

      The Oxford Latin Dictionary

      PG

      Patrologia cursus completus series graeca.

      Compiled by J.-P. Migne. Paris, 1857–1866.

      PIMS

      Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies (Toronto)

      xv

      xvi

      List of abbreviations

      PL

      Patrologia cursus completus series latina. Compiled

      by J.-P. Migne. Paris, 1841–1864.

      SC

      Sources chre´tiennes

      ST

      St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae

      STC

      A Short-Title Catalogue (Pollard and Redgrave)

      TLL

      Thesaurus linguae latinae

      Introduction

      When we think of our highest creative power, we think invariably of the

      imagination. ‘‘Great imagination, profound intuition,’’ we say: this is our

      highest accolade for intellectual achievement, even in the sciences. The

      memory, in contrast, is devoid of intellect: just memorization, not real

      thought or true learning. At best, for us, memory is a kind of photographic

      film, exposed (we imply) by an amateur and developed by a duffer, and so

      marred by scratches and inaccurate light-values.

      We make such judgments (even those of us who are hard scientists)

      because we have been formed in a post-Romantic, post-Freudian world, in

      which imagination has been identified with a mental unconscious of great,

      even dangerous, creative power. Consequently, when they look at the

      Middle Ages, modern scholars are often disappointed by the apparently

      lowly, working-day status accorded to imagination in medieval psychology –

      a sort of draught-horse of the sensitive soul, not even given intellectual status.

      Ancient and medieval people reserved their awe for memory. Their greatest

      geniuses they describe as people of s
    uperior memories, they boast unasham-

      edly of their prowess in that faculty, and they regard it as a mark of superior

      moral character as well as intellect.

      Because of this great change in the relative status of imagination and

      memory, many moderns have concluded that medieval people did not

      value originality or creativity. We are simply looking in the wrong place.

      We should instead examine the role of memory in their intellectual and

      cultural lives, and the values which they attached to it, for there we will get

      a firmer sense of their understanding of what we now call creative activity.

      The modern test of whether we really know something rests in our

      ability to use what we have been taught in a variety of situations (American

      pedagogy calls this ‘‘creative learning’’). In this characterization of learning,

      we concur with medieval writers, who also believed that education meant

      the construction of experience and method (which they called ‘‘art’’) out of

      knowledge. They would not, however, have understood our separation of

      1

      2

      The Book of Memory

      memory from learning. In their understanding of the matter, it was

      memory that made knowledge into useful experience, and memory that

      combined these pieces of information-become-experience into what we

      call ‘‘ideas,’’ what they were more likely to call ‘‘judgments.’’

      A modern experimental psychologist has written that ‘‘some of the best

      ‘memory crutches’ we have are called laws of nature,’’ for learning can be

      seen as a process of acquiring smarter and richer mnemonic devices to

      represent information, encoding similar information into patterns, organ-

      izational principles, and rules which represent even material we have never

      before encountered, but which is like what we do know, and thus can be

      recognized or remembered. 1 This is a position that older writers would

      have perfectly understood. It will be useful to begin my study by compar-

      ing descriptions of two men whom their contemporaries universally rec-

      ognized to be men of remarkable scientific genius (assessments which time

      has proven correct, though that is only partly relevant to my discussion):

      Albert Einstein and Thomas Aquinas. Each description is the testimony

      (direct or reported) of men who knew and worked intimately with them

     

    Prev Next
Read online free - Copyright 2016 - 2025