Read online free
  • Home
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Not Born Yesterday


    Prev Next




      NOT BORN YESTERDAY

      NOT

      BORN

      YESTERDAY

      the science of Who we trust

      and What we believe

      hugo mercier

      pr ince ton university pr ess

      pr ince ton & oxfor d

      Copyright © 2020 by Hugo Mercier

      Requests for permission to reproduce material from this work

      should be sent to permissions@press.princeton.edu

      Published by Prince ton University Press

      41 Wil iam Street, Prince ton, New Jersey 08540

      6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TR

      press .princeton .edu

      All Rights Reserved

      ISBN 978-0-691-17870-7

      ISBN (e- book) 978-0-691-19884-2

      British Library Cataloging- in- Publication Data is available

      Editorial: Sarah Caro, Charlie Allen, and Hannah Paul

      Production Editorial: Jenny Wolkowicki

      Text design: Leslie Flis

      Jacket design: Michel Vrana

      Production: Erin Suydam

      Publicity: Maria Whelan and Kate Farquhar- Thomson

      Jacket art: iStock

      This book has been composed in Arno Pro and Heading Smallcase Pro

      Printed on acid- free paper. ∞

      Printed in the United States of Amer ica

      10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

      To Thérèse Cronin

      CONTENTS

      List of Illustrations ix

      Acknowl edgments xi

      Introduction xiii

      1 The Case for Gullibility

      1

      2 Vigilance in Communication

      15

      3 Evolving Open- Mindedness

      30

      4 What to Believe?

      47

      5 Who Knows Best?

      63

      6 Who to Trust?

      78

      7 What to Feel?

      95

      8 Demagogues, Prophets, and Preachers

      113

      9 Propagandists, Campaigners, and Advertisers

      128

      10 Titil ating Rumors

      146

      vii

      viii con t en t s

      11 From Circular Reporting to Super natural Beliefs

      166

      12 Witches’ Confessions and Other Useful

      Absurdities 181

      13 Futile Fake News

      199

      14 Shallow Gurus

      217

      15 Angry Pundits and Skil ful Con Men

      240

      16 The Case against Gullibility

      257

      Notes 273

      References 307

      Index 351

      LIST OF ILLUSTR ATIONS

      Figure 1. The lines in the Asch conformity experiments.

      6

      Figure 2. “Bridge” strip from the webcomic xkcd

      by Randall Munroe.

      72

      Figure 3. Two examples of pareidolia: seeing faces

      where there are none.

      157

      Figure 4. What path does a ball launched at the arrow

      follow when it exits the tube?

      224

      ix

      ACKNOWL EDGMENTS

      the idea for this book stems from the article “Epistemic

      Vigilance,” written by Dan Sperber, Fabrice Clément, Christophe

      Heintz, Olivier Mascaro, Gloria Origgi, Deirdre Wilson, and my-

      self. In this article we suggested that humans are endowed with

      cognitive mechanisms dedicated to evaluating communicated

      information. I am particularly grateful to Dan Sperber— thesis

      supervisor, coauthor, mentor, friend. Besides having shaped my

      ideas through his writings and his discussions, he patiently read

      and gave me feedback on the book. Fabrice Clément had writ-

      ten his PhD thesis and a book— Les Mécanismes de la crédulité

      (The mechanisms of credulity)—on the same theme, and we

      discussed these issues when I was a postdoctoral researcher at

      the University of Neuchâtel. Besides Dan and Fabrice, the ideas

      in this book have been shaped by the feedback from the students

      of the Communication, Trust, and Argumentation class from

      2018 to 2019, and by discussions at the Department of Cognitive

      Studies of the ENS in Paris; the University of Pennsylvania; and

      the countless conferences, restaurants, pubs, and cafés where

      I’ve badgered people with the idea that humans aren’t gullible.

      Lila San Roque generously shared fantastic examples of eviden-

      tial use among the Duna, and I benefited from Chris Street’s

      knowledge of the lie detection lit er a ture.

      xi

      xi ackno w l edgmen t s

      My deepest thanks go to those who have commented on the

      whole, or parts of the manuscript: Sacha Altay (twice!), Stefaan

      Blancke, Pascal Boyer, Coralie Cheval ier, Thérèse Cronin (twice

      as well!), Guil aume Dezecache, Helena Miton, Olivier Morin,

      Thom Scott- Phil ips, Dan Sperber, and Radu Umbres.

      This book would not have existed without my agents John and

      Max Brockman, Sarah Caro, the editor who believed in the proj-

      ect from the start and provided very valuable feedback, as well

      as the team at Prince ton University Press.

      I have benefited from the financial backing of the Direction

      Générale de l’Armement (thanks to Didier Bazalgette in par tic-

      u lar); the Philosophy, Politics, and Economics program at the

      University of Pennsylvania (with the generous support of

      Steven F. Goldstone); the University of Neuchâtel’s Cognitive

      Science group and the Swiss National Science Foundation

      (Ambizione grant no. PZ00P1_142388); the Agence Nationale

      de la Recherche (grant EUR FrontCog ANR-17- EURE-0017

      to the DEC, and grant ANR-16- TERC-0001-01 to myself); and

      last but not least, the Centre National de la Recherche Scienti-

      fique, my current employer, allowing me to work in the amazing

      place that is the Jean Nicod Institute. In par tic u lar, the team I

      belong to— Evolution and Social Cognition, composed of Jean-

      Baptiste André, Nicolas Baumard, Coralie Chevallier, Olivier

      Morin, and our students, engineers, and postdocs— provides the

      best social and intellectual environment one could hope for.

      I will never stop thanking my parents, grandparents, and ex-

      tended family for their unwavering support. Christopher and

      Arthur are the best boys in the world; they have taught me much

      about love. They have also taught me that children aren’t gull-

      ible, even when we wish they’d be a bit easier to influence.

      Thérèse’s encouragement has meant more to me than I can

      ever communicate. Thank you for every thing.

      INTRODUCTION

      as i was walking back from university one day, a

      respectable- looking middle- aged man accosted me. He spun a

      good story: he was a doctor working in the local hospital, he had

      to rush to some urgent doctorly thing, but he’d lost his wallet,

      and he had no money for a cab ride. He was in dire need of twenty

      euros. He gave me his business card, told me I could call the num-

      ber and his secretary would wire the money back to me shortly.

      After some more cajoling I gav
    e him twenty euros.

      There was no doctor of this name, and no secretary at the end

      of the line.

      How stupid was I?

      And how ironic that, twenty years later, I would be writing a

      book arguing that people aren’t gullible.

      The Case for Gullibility

      If you think I’m gullible, wait until you meet, in the pages that

      follow, people who believe that the earth is a flat disk surrounded

      by a two- hundred- foot wall of ice, “Game of Thrones–style,”1 that

      witches poison their cattle with magical darts, that the local Jews

      kill young boys to drink their blood as a Passover ritual, that high-

      up Demo cratic operatives oversee a pedophile ring out of a

      xiii

      xiv in t roduc t ion

      pizza joint, that former North Korean leader Kim Jong-il could

      teleport and control the weather, or that former U.S. president

      Barack Obama is a devout Muslim.

      Look at all the gibberish transmitted through TV, books,

      radio, pamphlets, and social media that ends up being accepted

      by large swaths of the population. How could I possibly be claim-

      ing that we aren’t gullible, that we don’t accept what ever we read

      or hear?

      Arguing against widespread credulity puts me in the minor-

      ity. A long line of scholarship— from ancient Greece to twenty-

      first- century Amer ica, from the most progressive to the most

      reactionary— portrays the mass of people as hopelessly gullible.

      For most of history, thinkers have based their grim conclusions

      on what they thought they observed: voters submissively fol ow-

      ing demagogues, crowds worked up into rampages by blood-

      thirsty leaders, masses cowing to charismatic personalities. In the

      mid- twentieth century, psychological experiments brought more

      grist to this mil , showing participants blindly obeying author-

      ity, believing a group over the clear evidence of their own eyes.

      In the past few de cades, a series of sophisticated models have

      appeared that provide an explanation for human gullibility. Here

      is the core of their argument: we have so much to learn from

      others, and the task of figuring out who to learn from is so dif-

      ficult, that we rely on simple heuristics such as “follow the ma-

      jority” or “follow prestigious individuals.” Humans would owe

      their success as a species to their capacity to absorb their local

      culture, even if that means accepting some maladaptive practices

      or mistaken beliefs along the way.

      The goal of this book is to show this is all wrong. We don’t

      credulously accept what ever we’re told— even if those views are

      supported by the majority of the population, or by prestigious,

      in t r o d u c t i o n xv

      charismatic individuals. On the contrary, we are skilled at figur-

      ing out who to trust and what to believe, and, if anything, we’re

      too hard rather than too easy to influence.

      The Case against Gullibility

      Even if suggestibility might have some advantages in helping us

      acquire skil s and beliefs from our cultural environment, it is sim-

      ply too costly to be a stable, per sis tent state of affairs, as I wil

      argue in chapter 2. Accepting what ever others are communicat-

      ing only pays off if their interests are aligned with ours— think

      cel s in a body, bees in a beehive. As far as communication be-

      tween humans is concerned, such commonality of interests is

      rarely achieved; even a pregnant mother has reasons to mistrust

      the chemical signals sent by her fetus. Fortunately, there are ways

      of making communication work even in the most adversarial of

      relationships. A prey can convince a predator not to chase it. But

      for such communication to occur, there must be strong guaran-

      tees that those who receive the signal will be better off believing

      it. The messages have to be kept, on the whole, honest. In the case

      of humans, honesty is maintained by a set of cognitive mecha-

      nisms that evaluate communicated information. These mecha-

      nisms allow us to accept most beneficial messages—to be

      open— while rejecting most harmful messages—to be vigilant.

      As a result, I have called them open vigilance mechanisms, and they

      are at the heart of this book.2

      What about the “observations” used by so many scholars to

      make the case for gullibility? Most are merely popu lar miscon-

      ceptions. As the research reviewed in chapters 8 and 9 shows,

      those who attempt to persuade the masses— from demagogues

      to advertisers, from preachers to campaign operatives— nearly

      xvi in t roduc t ion

      always fail miserably. Medieval peasants in Eu rope drove many

      a priest to despair with their stubborn re sis tance to Christian pre-

      cepts. The net effect on presidential elections of sending flyers,

      robocalling, and other campaign tricks is close to zero. The sup-

      posedly all- powerful Nazi propaganda machine barely affected

      its audience—it couldn’t even get the Germans to like the Nazis.

      Sheer gullibility predicts that influence is easy. It is not. Stil ,

      indubitably, people sometimes end up professing the most ab-

      surd views. What we must explain are the patterns: why some

      ideas, including good ones, are so hard to get across, while others,

      including bad ones, are so popu lar.

      Mechanisms of Open Vigilance

      Understanding our mechanisms of open vigilance is the key to

      making sense of the successes and failures of communication.

      These mechanisms pro cess a variety of cues to tell us how much

      we should believe what we’re told. Some mechanisms examine

      whether a message is compatible with what we already believe

      to be true, and whether it is supported by good arguments. Other

      mechanisms pay attention to the source of the message: Is the

      speaker likely to have reliable information? Does she have my

      interests at heart? Can I hold her accountable if she proves

      mistaken?

      I review a wealth of evidence from experimental psy chol ogy

      showing how well our mechanisms of open vigilance function,

      including in small children and babies. It is thanks to these mech-

      anisms that we reject most harmful claims. But these mecha-

      nisms also explain why we accept a few mistaken ideas.

      For all their sophistication, and their capacity to learn and in-

      corporate novel information, our mechanisms of open vigilance

      in t r o d u c t i o n xvii

      are not infinitely malleable. You, dear reader, are in an informa-

      tion environment that differs in myriad ways from the one your

      ancestors evolved in. You are interested in people you’ll never

      meet (politicians, celebrities), events that don’t affect you (a di-

      saster in a distant country, the latest scientific breakthrough),

      and places you’ll never visit (the bottom of the ocean, galaxies

      far, far away). You receive much information with no idea of

      where it came from: Who started the rumor that Elvis wasn’t

      dead? What is the source of your parents’ religious beliefs? You

      are asked to pass judgment on views that had no practical rele- />
      vance whatsoever for our ancestors: What is the shape of the

      earth? How did life evolve? What is the best way to or ga nize a

      large economic system? It would be surprising indeed if our

      mechanisms of open vigilance functioned impeccably in this

      brave new, and decidedly bizarre, world.

      Our current informational environment pushes open vigi-

      lance mechanisms outside of their comfort zone, leading to

      mistakes. On the whole, we are more likely to reject valuable

      messages— from the real ity of climate change to the efficacy of

      vaccination— than to accept inaccurate ones. The main excep-

      tions to this pattern stem not so much from a failure of open vigi-

      lance itself, but from issues with the material it draws on. People

      sensibly use their own knowledge, beliefs, and intuitions to evalu-

      ate what they’re told. Unfortunately, in some domains our in-

      tuitions appear to be quite systematically mistaken. If you had

      nothing else to go on, and someone told you that you were stand-

      ing on a flat surface (rather than, say, a globe), you would spon-

      taneously believe them. If you had nothing else to go on, and

      someone told you all your ancestors had always looked pretty

      much like you (and not like, say, fish), you would spontaneously

      believe them. Many popu lar yet mistaken beliefs spread not

      xviii in t roduc t ion

      because they are pushed by masters of persuasion but because

      they are fundamentally intuitive.

      If the flatness of the earth is intuitive, a two- hundred- foot-

      high, thousands- of- miles- long wall of ice is not. Nor is, say, Kim

      Jong- il’s ability to teleport. Reassuringly, the most out- there be-

      liefs out there are accepted only nominally. I bet a flat- earther

      would be shocked to actually run into that two- hundred- foot

      wall of ice at the end of the ocean. Seeing Kim Jong-il being

      beamed Star Trek– style would have confused the hell out of the

      dictator’s most groveling sycophant. The critical question for un-

      derstanding why such beliefs spread is not why people accept

      them, but why people profess them. Besides wanting to share

      what we take to be accurate views, there are many reasons for

      professing beliefs: to impress, annoy, please, seduce, manipulate,

      reassure. These goals are sometimes best served by making state-

      ments whose relation to real ity is less than straightforward—or

      even, in some cases, statements diametrically opposed to the

     

    Prev Next
Read online free - Copyright 2016 - 2025